Jose wrote:Your citation of Gregory is interesting. Much as I admire his work, I find his summary that you cited for us (thank you) to be more semantics than substance.
Why should one expect anything different from someone who is espousing a panselectionist ideology by parroting the dogmas of strict extrapolationism? Gregory pretty much sums up the state of the world for Strict Extrapolationists like Jose, when he states,
Gregory wrote:Though the protagonists have often been divided along these professional lines, the micro-macro debate is not between paleontologists and population geneticists per se. Rather, it is between strict extrapolationists who argue that all evolution can be understood by studying population-level processes and those who argue that there are additional factors to consider. Members of this latter camp may come from all quarters of evolutionary biology, from genome biologists to paleontologists, although the latter have been by far the most vocal proponents of an expanded outlook. For strict extrapolationists, there may be little value in pursuing this debate. But for those open to a more pluralistic approach who seek a resolution to the issue, there is much value in understanding the arguments presented in favor of a distinct macroevolutionary theory that coexists with, but is not subsumed by, established microevolutionary principles. (
Gregory 2005: 686)
Ruse wrote:(....) [T]urning back to Darwin's writings, there were always some incredibly progressionist sentiments. Most notorious are the closing lines of the
Origin, which go right back to Darwin's earliest writings, namely his
Sketch of 1842 and his
Essay of 1844 (Darwin and Wallace 1958).
Darwin wrote:Thus, from the war of nature, from famine and death, the most exalted object which we are capable of conceiving, namely, the production of the higher animals, directly follows. There is grandeur in this view of life, with its several powers, having been originally breathed into a few forms or into one; and that, whilst this planet has gone cycling on according to the fixed law of gravity, form so simple a beginning endless forms most beautiful and most wonderful have been, and are being, evolved. (Darwin 1959, p. 490)
It is hard to imagine that these words are simply a rhetorical flourish. (Ruse 1988: 102-103)
(....) Darwin adopted some of the most sophisticated scientific thinking of his time, which argued that a tendency toward divergence and specialization is a mark of progress. Here, Darwin starts to sound remarkably like Spencer on heterogeneity, which is hardly surprising since they drew on the same sources. What Darwin did was to combine these two prongs, arguing that (in general) what competitive highness will lead to is precisely specialization. Hence, progress does indeed come out of a selection-driven evolutionary process.
Darwin wrote:If we look at the differentiation and specialization of the several organs of each being when adult (and this will include the advancements of the brain for intellectual purposes) as the best standard of highness of organization, natural selection clearly leads towards highness; for all phsiologists admit taht the specialization of organs, inasmuch as they perform in this state their functions better, is an advantage to each being; and hence the accumulation of variations tending towards specialization is within the scope of natural selection. (Darwin 1959, p. 222, 382.11:c)
(....) People who deny that Darwin was a progressionist -- and I was one of them (Ruse 1979) -- are just plain wrong. (Ruse 1988: 104)
Medawar wrote:To deride the hope of progress is the ultimate fatuity, the last word in poverty of spirit and meanness of mind. There is no need to be dismayed by the fact that we cannot yet envisage a definitive solution of our problems, a resting-place beyond which we need not try to go." -- Medawar 1972, p. 127
(....) [T]his paean to progression came in his [Medawar's] presidential address to the British Association, a point at which (by his own admission) he spoke "
of and
for science" (Medawar 1972, p. 9, his italics). I rest my case. (Ruse 1988: 122-123
-- Ruse, Michael (1988) Molecules to Men: Evolutionary Biology and Thoughts of Progress. In
Evolutionary Progress. Chicago. Pp. 97-123.
Some so-called scientists seek to impose the values of mechanistic materialism upon all interpretations of the facts. They want to portray their value choices as not being subjective, but being objective, when in reality their value choices are just as subjective as those of anyone else.
A perfect example of this fallacious form of reasoning (that one value choice is "objective" while another is "subjective") is found in the diversity of responses to the question of whether evolution is progressive or not; some scientists look at the facts and claim it is with respect to some specific criterion, while others claim it is not with respect to different criterion, and both make subjective value judgments when choosing which criterion to use.
Ayala wrote:The progress of evolution appears to be obviously progressive. The earliest organisms were no more complex than some bacteria and blue-green algae. Three billion years later, their descendents include orchids, bees, peacocks and human beings, which appear to be more complex, advanced, or progressive than their ancestors. (Ayala 1988: 75)
Upon reflection the issue becomes less obvious, because what do we mean when we say there has been progress in the evolutionary process? Some evolutionary lineages do not appear progressive at all: living bacteria are not very different from their ancestors of two or three billion years earlier. In addition, extinction can hardly be progressive, yet most evolutionary lineages have become extinct. Still more, organisms may be progressive with respect to others. For example, bacteria are able to synthesize all their own components and obtain the energy they need for living from inorganic compounds; human beings depend on other organisms. (Ayala 1988: 75)
(....) The term "change" means alteration, whether in the position, the state, or the nature of a thing. Progress implies change, but not vice versa; not all changes are progressive. (Ayala 1988: 76)
(....) "Evolution" and "progress" can also be distinguished, although both imply that sustained change has occurred. Evolutionary change is not necessarily progressive. The evolution of a species may lead to its own extinction, a change which is not progressive, at least not for that species. (Ayala 1988: 76)
(....) The notion of progress requires that a value judgment be made about what is better and what is worse, or what is higher and what is lower, according to some axiological standard. (Ayala 1988: 78)
(....) Uniform progress takes place whenever every later member of the sequence is better than every earlier member of the sequence according to a certain feature. (Ayala 1988: 79)
(....) Net progress does not require that every member of the sequence be better than all previous members of the sequence and worse than all its successors; it requires only that later members of the sequence be better, on the average, than earlier members. Net progress allows for temporary fluctuations of value.... Some authors have argued that progress has not occurred in evolution because no matter what standard is chosen, fluctuations can always be found in every evolutionary lineage. This argument is valid against the occurrence of uniform progress, but not against the existence of net evolutionary progress. (Ayala 1988: 79)
(....) General progress is that which occurs in all historical sequences of a given domain of reality and from the beginning of the sequences until their end. Particular progress is that which occurs in one or several but not all historical sequences, or that which takes place during part but not all of the duration of the sequences. (Ayala 1988: 80)
Some writers have denied that evolution is progressive on the grounds that not all evolutionary lineages exhibit advance. Some evolutionary lineages, like those leading to certain parasitic forms, are retrogressive by certain standards; and ... have lineages have become extinct without issue. These considerations are valid against a claim of general progress, but not against claims of particular forms of progress. (Ayala 1988: 80-81)
[T]he notion of progress is axiological and, therefore, it cannot be a strictly scientific term: value judgments are not part and parcel of scientific discourse, which is characterized by empirically testable hypotheses and objective descriptions. (Ayala 1988: 81)
(....)
Human Consciousness: Climax of One Kind of Progress
Once one realizes that recognition of progress is only possible after a value judgment has been made as to which will be the standard against which progress is to be measured (and hence, that there is not a standard of progress, or one that is best for all purposes), it becomes possible to seek standards of progress that may yield valuable insights into the study of the evolution of life. (Ayala 1988: 90)
I shall now, by way of illustration, discuss progress according to a particular standard of reference: the ability of an organism to obtain and process information about the environment. I can see two reasons that make this criterion of progress especially meaningful (although not, I reiterate, the most meaningful, because no criterion exists that is best for all purposes). First, the ability to obtain information about the environment and to react accordingly, is an important adaptation, because it allows the organism to seek out suitable environments and resources and to avoid unsuitable ones. Second, because the ability to perceive the environment, and to integrate, coordinate, and react flexibly to what is perceived, has attained its highest development in mankind. This incomparable advancement is perhaps the most fundamental characteristic that sets apart Homo sapiens from all other animals. Symbolic language, complex social organization, control over the environment, the ability to envisage future states and to work towards them, values and ethics are developments made possible by man's greatly developed capacity to obtain and organize information about the state of the environment. This capacity has ushered in mankind's new mode of adaptation. Whereas other organisms become genetically adapted to their environments, humans create environments to fit their genes. It is thus that mankind has spread over the whole planet in spite of its physiological dependence on a tropical or subtropical climate. (Ayala 1988: 90-91)
Increased ability to gather and process information about the environment is sometimes expressed as evolution towards “independence from the environment.” (….) The notion of “control over the environment” also has been associated with the ability to gather and use information about the state of the environment. However, true control over the environment occurs to any substantial extent only in the human species. All organisms interact with the environment, but they do not control it…. The ability to control the environment started with the australopithecines, the first group of organisms which may be called human: some were able to produce devices to manipulate the environment in the form of rudimentary pebble and bone tools. The ability to obtain and process information about the conditions of the environment does not provide control over the environment but rather it enables the organisms to avoid unsuitable environmenents and to seek suitable ones. It has developed in many organisms because it is a useful adaptation. (Ayala 1988: 91-92)
Some selective interaction with the environment occurs in all organisms. The cell memebrane of a bacterium permits certain molecules but not others to enter the cell. Selective molecular exchange occurs also in the inorganic world; but this can hardly be called a form of information processing. Certain bacteria when placed on a agar plate move about in a zig-zag pattern, which is almost certainly random. The most rudimentary ability to gather and process information about the environment may be found in certain single-celled eukaryotes (= organisms with a true nucleus). A Paramecium follows a sinuous path as it swims, ingesting the bacteria that it encounters. Whenever it meets unfavorable conditions, like unsuitable acidity or salinity in the water, the Paramecium checks its advance, turns and starts in a new direction. Its reaction is purely negative. The Paramecium apparently does not seek its food or a favorable environment, but simply avoids unsuitable conditions. (Ayala 1988: 92)
Euglena, also a single-celled organism, exhibits a somewhat greater ability to process information about the environment. Euglena has a light-sensitive spot by means of which it can orient itself towards the light. Euglena's motions are directional; it not only avoids unsuitable environments but it actively seeks suitable ones. An amoeba represents further progress in the same direction; it reacts to light by moving away from it, and also actively pursues food particles. (Ayala 1988: 92)
An increase in the ability to gather and process information about the environment is not a general characteristic of the evolution of life. Progress has occurred in certain evolutionary lines but not in others. Today's bacteria are not more progressive by this criterion than their ancestors of three billion years ago. In many evolutionary sequences some very limited progress took place in the very early stages, without further progress through the rest of their history. In general, animals are more advanced than plants; vertebrates are more advanced than invertebrates; mammals are more advanced than reptiles, which are more advanced than fish. The most advanced organism by this criterion is doubtless the human species. (Ayala 1988: 92-93)
The ability to obtain and to process information about the environment has progressed little in the plant kingdom. Plants react to light and to gravity. The geotropism is positive in the root, but negative in the stem. Plants also grow towards the light; some plants like hte sunflower have parts which follow the course of the sun through its daily cycle. Another tropism in plants is the tendency of roots to grow towards water. The response to gravity, to water, and to light is basically due to differential growth rates; a greater elongation of cells takes place on one side of the root or stem than on the other side. Gradients of light, gravity or moisture are the clues which guide these tropism. Some plants react also to tactile stimuli. Tendrils twine around what they touch; Mimosa and carnivorous plants like the Venus flytrap (Dionaea) have leaves which close upon being touched. (Ayala 1988: 93)
A limited form of coordinated behavior occurs in the echinoderms which comprise the starfishes and sea urchins. Whereas coelenterates possess only an undifferentiated nerve net, echinoderms possess a nerve net, a nerve ring, and radial nerve cords. When the appropriate stimulus is encountered, a starfish reacts with direct and unified actions of the whole body. (Ayala 1988: 93)
The most primitive form of a brain occurs in certain organisms like planarian flatworms, which also have numerous sensory cells and eyes without lenses. The information gathered in these sensory cells and organs is processed and coordinated by the central nervous system and the rudimentary brain; a planarian worm is capable of some variability of responses and of some simple learning. That is, the same stimuli will not necessarily always produce the same response. (Ayala 1988: 93)
Planarian flatworms have progressed farther than starfishes in the ability to gather and process information about the environment, and the starfishes have progressed farther than sea anenomes and other coelenterates. But none of these organisms has gone very far by this criterion of progress. The most progressive groups of organisms among the invertebrates are te cephalopods and arthropods, but the vertebrates have progressed much farther than any invertebrates. (Ayala 1988: 93-94)
Among the ancestors of both the arthopods and the vertebrates, there were organisms that, like the sponges, lacked a nervious system. These ancestors evolved through a stage with only a simple network, whereas later stages developed a central nervous system and eventually a rudimentary brain. With further development of the central nervous system and of the brain, the ability to obtain and process information from outside progressed much father. The anthropods, which include the insects, have complex forms of behavior. Precise visual, chemical and acoustic signals are obtained and processed by many arthopods, particularly in their search for food and in their selection of mates. (Ayala 1988: 94)
Vertebrates are generally able to obtain and process much more complicated signals and to produce a much greater variety of responses than arthopods. The vertebrate brain has an enormous number of associative neurons with an extremely complex arrangement. Among the vertebrates, progress in the ability to deal with environmental information is correlated with increase in the size of the cerebral hemispheres and with the appearance and development of the "neopallium." The neopallium is involved in association and coordination of all kinds of impulses from all receptors and brain centers. The larger brain of vertebrates, compared to that of invertebrates, permits them also to have a large amount of neurons involved in information storage or memory. The neopallium appeared first in the reptiles. In the mammals it has expanded to become the cerebral cortex, which covers most of the cerebral hemispheres. The cerebral cortex in humans is particularly large, compressed over the hemispheres in a complex pattern of folds and turns. When organisms are measured by their ability to process and obtain information about the environment, mankind is, indeed, the most progressive organism on earth. (Ayala 1988: 94)
(....) Mankind is not the most progressive species by many criteria. By some standards, humans are among the bottom rungs of the ladder of life, for example, in the ability to synthesize their own biological materials from inorganic resources. (Ayala 1988: 95)
(....) "progressive" is an evaluative term that demands a subjective commitment to a particular standard of value. (Ayala 1988: 95)
-- Ayala, Fancisco J. Can "Progress" be Defined as a Biological Concept? In Evolutionary Progress (ed., Matthew H. Nitecki). Chicago: University of Chicago Press; 1988; pp. 75-96.
McMenamin wrote:When brainy, motile animals appeared, the members of other kingdoms were driven into deeper water or slowly driven to extinticion.... Ediacarans were on the verge, by the end of the Lipalian period, of developing forms with cephalized bilateral symmetry: anterior sense organs and a brain fomed by cell family fusion. Spriggina and Marywadea are essentially encephalized versions of Dickinsonia. This evolutionary development was totally independent of metazoans.
-- McMenamin, Mark A. S. Discovering the First Complex Life: The Garden of Ediacara. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1998; c1998
It should be noted that we now understand more about the
Hox genes and the genetic pathways comprising an ancient architecture laid down ove 450 million years ago which facilitated the evolution of the Central Nervious System.
Jose wrote:Wilson's nice, from-the-heart intuition is at odds with the data. If we wanted to be scientific about this, rather than philosophical or religious, we'd have to go with the data: "Progress" is not a necessary property of evolution.
Mechanistic materialists, like Gould, Dawkins, Jose et al., impose their own value judgments upon the facts of organic evolution by valuing some facts (criterion) more than others, and then fallaciously attempting to claim that there own value judgments (choices of criterion) are "objective," while those who see progress based upon other criterion are making "subjective" choices, "nice from-the-heart intuition ... [which are] at odds with the data." In truth and fact, both require value judgments when choosing which criterion by which to evaluate the question of progress, except it is more honest to openly admit this is the case.
Jose's claim that his value choice is objective and according to the data is shown to be patently false by Ayala's statements above; the evolution of the Central Nervous System is just as much a fact and datum as any other criterion which one selects, and it requires a value judgment to determine which criterion one will use. The truth is that it requires a value judgment when addressing the question of progress, and whether one comes out con or pro, both require a subjective value judgment in choosing which criterion one will use to answer this question.
It is also fallacious to claim, or imply, as Jose does, that scientists don't make subjective value judgments in evaluating the so-called "facts" of science.
Such mechanistic materialists attempt to use the cloak of so-called "scientific authority" to claim the subjective value choices they are espousing are "scientific," when in reality they are espousing implicit value judgments and subjective philosophical and metaphysical choices, a viewpoint that is not science but scientism.
Allen wrote:Philosophically, Morgan was not only an empiricist and a staunch experimentalist. He was also fundamentally a skeptic and materialist. His skepticism took the particular turn, as it did for many biologists of his generation, of strong antireligious feelings. Morgan was judicious (or diplomatic) enough never to write openly about his hostility to religion, but it emerged clearly in his personal conversation, and sometimes subtly in his writings. Religion was to Morgan, like Driesch's entelechy or other vitalistic notions, a form of mystery. The role of science, of biology in particular, was to combat mystery, and that meant, particularly in the context of late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century America, to combat religion. Morgan was militantly antireligious. As Dobzhansky, who worked with Morgan both at Columbia and Cal Tech, wrote: "Now, about his militant atheism -- his idea was religion feeds on mystery. The way to combat religion is to combat mystery, hence to show that the biological phenomena are not mysterious, but they are scientifically explicable. That was the reason why Morgan worked in biology, particularly in genetics and evolution" (1962, p. 255). Morgan's strong antireligious feelings may well be the source of much of his philosophy of science -- of his materialism, his experimentalism, his emphasis on physicochemical explanations. The bearing of this attitude on Morgan's evolutionary views may very well be that to combat religious views on creation, biology must be careful no tot fall into the same trap of inventing obscure or abstract "principles," "factors," or other nonentities to account for the diversity and adaptation of life. Scientists must remember that they are nothing more than priests of a new religion if they think that by naming something they have explained its existence. Even a term like selection could represent the error of explaining by naming if there were no empirical data to support its existence. Morgan's philosophy of science ... stood on an empirical foundation of its own, but the view may have been formed initially, and was certainly fed continuously, by his strong opposition to religion and mystical explanations of any kind.
-- Allen, Garland E. The Evolutionary Synthesis: Morgan and Natural Selection Revisited. In The Evolutionary Synthesis: Perspectives on the Unification of Biology. (eds., Ernst Mayr and William B. Provine). Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1980; p. 379.
As the above quotation makes clear, science is
not value free simply because science is an activity in the minds of scientists, and like all humans, we operate within an intellectual framework which in the end is
subjectively value conditioned by philosophical choices of the individual scientist.
If one is a mechanistic materialist, and discounts the value of conscious minds which are able to discriminate meanings and values, than from this reductionistic framework it is rather easy to discount the data/evidence observed in the fact of the evolution of increasingly complex Central Nervous Systems in organisms, and the increasing role that conscious intelligence plays in evolution by allowing an organism to control its environment and to thereby increasingly determine the course of its own evolution.
But as anyone who reads the scientific literature widely and deeply observes, the fact remains, there is a diversity of views within the scientific community with regards to this question of whether or not the fact of organic evolution is in truth progressive, and it requires a value judgment in making the choice as to which criterion one uses in addressing it.
And I note that the perfect evidence that Jose is not motivated by an honest examination of the facts that there is a diversity of views within the scientific community, such as those of Ayala, McMenamin, Ruse, et al., or honestly willing to admit that Ayala is correct that evaluating this question requires a value choice, but rather resorts to the disingenious tactic of misrepresenting and distorting Ayala and McMenamin's arguments, implying that they argued there was an "Intelligent Force that, perhaps, covers certain bases in the DNA and makes them non-mutable." Such a claim is a philosophical one and beyond the ability of science to answer, but of course, Jose knows this, which all the more reveals his disingenous intentions, which tells us a lot what malicious and deceptive agenda is driving Jose.